IMMANUEL KANT AND THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE

Shandon L. Guthrie

INTRODUCTION

For some time now philosophers have discussed the possibility of the existence of right and wrong. Such words have been associated with morality and ethical decision-making. Various theories have been offered representing all points of the ethics spectrum in an attempt to answer the question, "Do morals exist?" The great German Idealist philosopher of the Nineteenth century, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), gave considerable thought to this question.

In this paper I will present and critically analyze Kant's view of meta-ethics(1) in order to determine if he has successfully addressed reasons why we ought to accept his moral point of view. Before such an analysis and evaluation can be given, I will give some definitions for the purposes extant in this paper. When we say ethics we mean theories or systems that reflect personal actions, decisions, and relations. Morality refers to the belief and conformity of acts of right and wrong. For example, ethics refers to such systems as Utilitarianism and Hedonism and morality refers to such things as "lying is wrong" and "it is good to be sacrificial." Although these definitions are not exclusively for these examples, their meaning is strictly to convey the idea that there is a difference between a classification of systems and an identification of what a system believes, respectively. For most people, ethics and morality are used interchangeably. This will be the case in this paper as well. Finally, while we hear about ethical systems that are teleologicalwe will only be interested in the branched ethical system that is commonly referred to as being deontological.(2) The precise interpretation of how one ought to classify Kant in regard to his ethical theory will be considered in this work as well.

THE CONCEPT OF DUTY

The particular work under consideration will be Kant's Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals translated by H.J. Paton. This work, although relatively short, contains Kant's working definition of his concept of morality. In addition, a portion of Kant's work, Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative that is in his Foundations, will be included in our discussion from Anthony Serafini's compilation of ethical essays, Ethics and Social Concern. For Kant, the central focus of morality is along the lines of obligation or reasons of ought. If it is defined in terms of ought, we must understand if conditional or unconditional usages are being applied here. That is, a conditional ought means that one ought to perform some act in order for something else to happen (i.e. possibly some type of reward). If something is an unconditional ought then one ought to perform some act apart from any consideration of merit.

It appears that Kant himself adopts the view that morality is the unconditional ought. It is without regard to reward or merit. Dr. Ed. L. Miller of the University of Colorado states:

For Kant, only the unconditional ought is the moral ought. Why? Because, as we all
recognize--don't we?--morality must be necessary and universal, that is, it must be
absolutely binding, and absolutely binding on everyone alike: Whoever you are, what-
ever your situation, you ought to do X.(3)

The implication here is that moral acts are to be accomplished apart from any alternate considerations such as merit and reward. In fact, Miller mentions that this means morality must be "binding" and "universal." After all there would be something wrong with the idea that "murder is wrong" applies to person Q and not person R. Indeed, Kant himself states:

I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim should become
universal law. Here, now, it is the simple conformity to law in general, without assuming
any particular law applicable to certain actions, that serves the will as its principle, and
must so serve it, if duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimeric vision.(4)

Kant further dismisses the notion that morality operates in a meritocracy:

the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect expected from it, nor
in any principle of action which requires to borrow its motive from this ex-
pected effect.(5)

When one understands the departure of a moral act from its consequences, it becomes clear what Kant was attempting to convey. This is what he and others refer to as duty. The fulfillment of our duty then does not rest on the consequences of our actions. However, the results of an action may be necessary in determining duty, but this is not to be confused with the consequences that result from human action. In the terms of Nineteenth century philosophy, the results of the thing-in-itself (the moral act) affect both the subject (the moral agent) and the object (the other individual/individuals affected). By making the act universal and necessary, the highest good must be achieved in the subject-object relationship. This determines what our duty is. In understanding what the proper ideal is in the maximization of the highest good of each action we look through it in our perception of the world and how we ought to act in it. This brings us to the next section.

MORALITY AS A PRIORI

Kant emphasizes the absolute necessity of separating genuine morality from all empirical considerations, and instead the necessity of deriving it a priori, or from the categorization of claims alleged to be true apart from experiencing them first, from pure reason. For Kant, morality must be a priori. If it is not, then morality falls into the realm of "anthropology" or empirical truths about human nature. This means that morality must be "freed from everything which may be only empirical"(6) For Kant, morality simply must be separate from experience due to the very idea of duty itself. In his Foundations Kant makes this argument:

Everyone must admit that a law, if it is to hold morally, i.e., as a ground of obligation,
must imply absolute necessity; he must admit that the command, "Thou shalt not lie,"
does not apply to men only, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it. The
same is true for all other moral laws properly so called.(7)

Again, the clear message of duty's transcendence of human experience becomes the idea shared by all rational beings. So, if all of us are wearing the rose-colored glasses of morality (the idea), then the world must look rose-colored in morality to all of us (the projection). If morality appears to exist universally, then it seems that all of us share the same idea, namely that morality exists a priori. This is how Kant's ethical system roots itself in the a priori assumption. Since Kant's system is known a priori, than presents us with a universal and necessary view of morality in the world. It might be said that morality is discovered rather than invented in Kantian ethics.

THE "GOOD WILL"

Kant gives a concise definition of what he believes, but the matter remains as to where these a priori assumptions derive from. Graciously enough, Kant has provided a foundation for these intuitions about morality, namely the "Good Will." Indeed, Kant states:

Nothing in the world--indeed nothing even beyond the world--can possibly be con-
ceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will.(8)

As seen in alternate ethical systems, such things as pleasure and happiness are seen as basic virtues or foundations of moral action (and in some cases its motive). But Kant wishes to avoid linking moral intuition to natural proclivities such as these. Rather, morality must be rationally conceived apart from our human inclinations. Kant, through analogy, shows why morality cannot be based on such inclinations:

Intelligence, wit, judgment, and the other talents of the mind, however they be
named, or courage, resoluteness, and perseverance as qualities of temperament,
are doubtless in many respects good and desirable. But they can become extremely
bad and harmful if the will, which is to make use of these gifts of nature and which
in its special constitution is called character, is not good.(9)

What he is saying here is that just as qualities such as intelligence, wit, and judgment are neutral tools of the person, so are pleasure and happiness. It could be the case that pleasure and happiness motivate evil or morally forbidden acts. Slavery in one sense made many Europeans happy but such acts are undeniably sinister to most people today. Dr. Miller explains what Kant connotes in the concept of the good will:

For Kant a good will, or a pure will, is an intention to act in accordance with moral
law, and moral law is what it is no matter what anything else is. To act out of a good
will is, then, to do X because it is right to do X, and for no other reason. This
would be rational morality.(10)

In analysis to Kant's motivation by the good will to enact a duty differs from acting in accordance with duty. Such difference neglects motivation. For example, someone who saves the life of a woman from a murderous man in order that he may rob her may be considered to act only in accordance with duty in regard to her deliverance from the murderer. He did not act out of the good will since his motivation was to rob her. Therefore, to take both intent and motivation into account in order to do the right thing considers one to be acting morally or out of duty. This act is said to proceed from the good will.

THE "CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE"

One final thought remains in Kant's ethical system. Having presented his view on how and why something may be considered moral, the issue of examination caps the end of his view in this section. That is, Kant presents us with a test or a method of determination on whether or not a particular act is considered to be morally right, morally wrong, or somewhere beyond the moral realm. For Kant it is the categorical imperative. An imperative is said to be either hypotheticalor categorical. Kant writes, "If now the action is good only as a means to something else, then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is conceived as good in itself and consequently as being necessarily the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then it is categorical . . . ."(11) So he says that in order for an act to be categorically imperative, it must be thought to be good in itself and in conformity to reason. As a categorical imperative, it asks us whether or not we can "universalize" our actions, that is, whether it would be the case that others would act in accordance with the same rule in a similar circumstance. This is seen in Kant's statement about the categorical imperative:

Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should
become a universal law.(12)

The point Kant makes in his presentation of the categorical imperative is that an act becomes imperative (or commanded) because it is the right thing to do. Miller comments:

a categorical imperative would command you to do X inasmuch as X is intrins-
ically right, that is, right in and of itself, aside from any other considerations--no
"ifs," no conditions, no strings attached . . . a categorical imperative is uncon-
ditional (no "ifs") and independent of any things, circumstances, goals, or desires.
It is for this reason that only a categorical imperative can be a universal and
binding law, that is, a moral law, valid for all rational beings at all times.(13)

This is to say that because a moral act is the right thing to do, it is universal and binding on the agent to follow through with the moral act. However, the act should not be done out of any condition ("ifs" or "if . . . thens").

With the categorical imperative as the fundamental principle of morality, it becomes the impetus for determining whether an act is moral or not. At this point it should be emphasized that Kant's categorical imperative is concerned only with general and abstract moral acts. Therefore, the categorical imperative determines whether or not any act is right or wrong. It is at this point that to do the opposite (to not will to do an act that everyone in similar circumstances would do) would be to invite contradiction. That is, something is wrong when it would result in a contradiction. By contradiction we are not referring to a logical one (i.e. A = [~A]) but a practical one (i.e. when something is self-defeating). Kant himself uses four examples of this, one of which illustrates the point. He posits a man in extreme despair who considers whether or not he should take his own life.(14) The dilemma is this: Either he takes his own life thereby thwarting the threat of ongoing dissatisfaction or he remains alive to face his situation. Kant states that the nature of feeling "despair" is one which impels one to improve live (e.g. feeling bad requires one to do something to feel good). If he chooses to take his own life, he is actually universalizing the maxim, "In order to love myself, I should shorten my life." This maxim is a practical contradiction because the consequent works opposite to the antecedent. That is, killing myself does nothing to improve my life. It results in a contradiction. In this sense the categorical imperative is used as a test for general moral principles in order to determine a particular act based on its own general maxim. The criterion for a particular action is found in its general principle. This general principle is tested to be either a contradiction or a morally permissible act. Consequently, the nature of the action is determined from this setup.

In summary, Immanuel Kant's metaethical system relies on the fundamental realization of the moral law that exists in the agent (subject). When we view the world (the object) we know a priori that morality is universal and necessary. In order to determine whether or not a particular act is good or bad, morally speaking, we must apply the categorical imperative. This imperativeor command requires that we fulfill our duty in the circumstance the act is occurring in. The classification of the act rests on whether or not the underlying principle is a practical contradiction. If it is not then the act is considered to be morally obligatory.

EVALUATION AND ASSESSMENT

While Kant has indeed shaped modern thought on moral decision-making, not all moralists have accepted his deontological system. In this section I will briefly address three criticisms of Kant's moral system.

First, philosophers have properly targeted the basic problem with Kant's system, namely that it neglects to identify or, rather, to justify the existence of the moral law. Is there some undergirding morality that provides a foundation for a belief in a moral law? I would answer the question in the affirmative but not based upon Kant's justification for moral theory. It may be that Kant would answer the question by giving a discourse on why metaphysical postulations are independent of theoretical reason.(15) Whatever one's view of Kant's epistemological Idealism, I believe that there is a substantial reason to accept the moral law. My view agrees with Kant's system which goes beyond the mere Immanent Purpose and Transcendentalism views. My view rests on Christian theism that suggests that we ought to postulate a Law-giver before we can require human beings to obey any law. The decision is arbitrary to follow the moral point of view if we assume that morality is simply the moral "furniture" that exists. Reasons for why I do not accept the existence of morals as brute givens but, rather, for reasons that are God-given are: 1) There is no reason to choose it over other views such as nihilism or utilitarianism. It simply has nothing to offer over the other views; 2) Moral responsibility seems to imply free will. It is unclear why one "ought" to do something if he or she has no ability whatsoever to do it. Free will makes the most sense on the assumption of substance dualism (the belief that human beings are made of two substances: body and spirit). Substance dualism makes more sense if theism is true. Even though Kant himself accepted theism, I believe that it makes more sense to ground morality in God; and 3) Kant's system does not explain other transcendental aspects of moral decision-making. For example, we experience guilt feelings and feelings of shame and remorse. These feelings go beyond what would be appropriate if only another human being were involved. H.P. Owen argues that on this basis guilt feelings do not make sense in the presence of mere abstract moral principles. Rather, they make more sense in the presence of a Person.(16)

Second, Some have objected that Kant's system neglects the value of nature. That is, since Kant's system treats human beings as ends-in-themselves, then the threat of abusing nature and what might be considered valuable may be neglected (i.e. animal rights, environmental issues, etc. . .). In response I would suggest a couple of points. First, it begs the question by assuming that other issues carry no moral weight in moral decision-making. But others have demonstrated that Kantian ethics does consider these issues. Second, this is no objection to Kant's system as a whole. Rather, it only shows, at best, a particular shortcoming or flaw in its methodology. It may be that an addendum ought to be tacked on in order to compensate for these "neglected" areas but this in no way detracts from the truth of the role of duty. Finally, Kant's system emphasizes a greater value in human beings over environmental and natural entities. But this is not to be confused with objects of no value (e.g. rocks, tables, etc. . .).

Finally, philosophers have attempted to bring consequences back into the moral system. They believe that consequences cannot be ignored despite Kantian ethics. There may be some further consideration needed; however, it is not required to apply consequences. Assessing moral issues ought to be defined in terms of the acts in themselves. Consequences actually are not taken into consideration in most instances. If I lie in order to protect a Jew during the holocaust from a Nazi affiliate, then I am not accepting consequence over duty (i.e. the duty not to lie). Instead I am preserving a "higher" duty to preserve human life. The former duty (the duty not to lie) is not being ignored but, rather, trumped by this greater need. This is why consequences are rarely considered.

Therefore, I find Kant's metaethical system a valuable tool that neglects to define moral law as God-given. I believe that the belief in theism is required in order better establish purpose and ought to moral decision-making. All in all, Kantian ethics provides a fantastic basis for current ethical issues and moral dilemmas we face today and issues we will probably face for years to come.

END NOTES

1. Meta-ethics is the area of philosophical reasoning determining the existence of ethics.

2. Teleological theories emphasize intended consequences or outcomes of actions for determining moral value. Deontological theories use intent to perform one's duty through a moral action.

3. Miller, p. 454.

4. Kant, ed. Serafini, p. 29.

5. Ibid., p. 28.

6. Kant, ed. Paton, p. 27.

7. Ibid.

8. Ibid., p. 9.

9. Ibid.

10. Miller, p. 461.

11. Kant, ed. Serafini, p. 31.

12. Ibid.

13. Miller, p. 462.

14. See Kant, ed. Serafini, p. 32.

15. See Miller, p. 255.

16. Owen, pp. 49-50.