Chapter Seven--Monopoly Capitalism and Imperialism
Introduction: Elite Reaction to Crisis (with Digression on Maldistribution of Income)
William Appleman Williams summarized the lesson of the 1890s in this way: "Because of its dramatic and extensive nature,
the Crisis of the 1890's raised in many sections of American society the specter of chaos and revolution."1
American economic elites saw it as the result of overproduction and surplus capital, and believed it could be resolved only
through access to a "new frontier." Without state-guaranteed access to foreign markets, output would be too far below capacity,
unit costs would be driven up, and unemployment would reach dangerous levels.
The seriousness of the last threat was underscored by the radicalism of the Nineties. The Pullman Strike, Homestead, and
the formation of the Western Federation of Miners (precursor to the IWW) were signs of dangerous levels of labor unrest and
class consciousness. Coxey's Army marched on Washington, a small foretaste of the kinds of radicalism that could be produced
by unemployment. The anarchist movement had a growing foreign component, more radical than the older native faction, and the
People's Party seemed to have a serious chance of winning national elections. At one point Jay Gould, the mouthpiece of the
robber barons, was threatening a capital strike (much like those in Venezuela recently) if the populists came to power. In
1894 businessman F. L. Stetson warned, "We are on the edge of a very dark night, unless a return of commercial prosperity
relieves popular discontent."2
We should note, in passing, that from a mutualist perspective the roots of over-accumulation go much deeper than Stromberg's
description of cartelization under monopoly capitalism. The origin of overproduction and over-accumulation lies in the legal
privileges of "laissez-faire" capitalism, described under the headings of Tucker's "Big Four" in the last chapter.
J.A. Hobson, in his brilliant chapter on "The Economic Taproot of Imperialism," ascribed the problem to mal-distribution
of purchasing power. Ever greater incomes had been concentrated in the hands of the plutocracy, who were unable to dispose
of it on any conceivable amount of luxury; the result was that "a process of automatic saving set in..." This had the
effect of exacerbating the problem of excess capital accumulation, expanding production facilities still further to produce
even more output for which there was no demand. "The power of production has far outstripped the actual rate of consumption...."3
The excess of accumulation and shortfall in demand, by disrupting the circuit of capital and creating what Marx called a crisis
of realization, led to a worsening business cycle.
In response to his rhetorical question of why over-saving and under-consumption occurred, and consumption failed
to keep pace with productive capacity, Hobson pointed to the social system.
But it may be asked, "Why should there be any tendency to over-saving? why should the owners of consuming power withhold
a larger quantity for savings than can be serviceably employed?" Another way of putting the same question is this, "Why should
not the pressure of present wants keep pace with every possibility of satisfying them? The answer to these pertinent questions
carries us to the broadest issue of the distribution of wealth. If a tendency to distribute income or consuming power according
to needs is operative, it is evident that consumption would rise with every rise of producing power, for human needs are illimitable,
and there could be no excess of saving. But it is quite otherwise in a state of economic society where distribution has no
fixed relation to needs, but is determined by other conditions which assign to some people a consuming power vastly in excess
of needs or possible uses, while others are destitute of consuming power enough to satisfy even the full demands of physical
efficiency.4
Over-saving results almost entirely from the surplus income of the rich.5
The question remains, what is the reason for this mal-distribution of income? Hobson approached, without ever reaching,
an adequate explanation.
The over-saving which is the economic root of Imperialism is found by analysis to consist of rents, monopoly profits, and
other unearned or excessive elements of income, which, not being earned by labour of head or hand, have no legitimate raison
d'être. Having no natural relation to effort of production, they impel their recipients to no corresponding satisfaction
of consumption: they form a surplus wealth, which, having no proper place in the normal economy of production and consumption,
tends to accumulate as excessive savings.6
Hobson proposed, in response to this deficiency, what would later be called a Keynesian solution:
Let any turn in the tide of politico-economic forces divert from these owners their excess of income and make it flow,
either to the workers in higher wages, or to the community in taxes, so that it will be spent instead of being saved... there
will be no need to fight for foreign markets or foreign areas of investment....
Where the distribution of incomes is such as to enable all classes of the nation to convert their felt wants into an effective
demand for commodities, there can be no over-production, no under-employment of capital and labour, and no necessity to fight
for foreign markets.7
Hobson's reference to the divorce of consumption from the effort of production might have been written by Tucker. The natural
wage of labor, when the state does not specially privilege ownership of land and capital, is its product. When labor receives
its full product in payment for work done, the disutility of labor is directly related to its product by market price. The
laborer is able to decide how much to work, based on how much he wants to consume--and to cease work when his needs are met.
Whatever savings are made reflect the worker's own decision to work less in the future, either by living off present savings
or by investing them in more efficient production. No superfluity is ever created. But under the capitalist system of privilege,
the divorce of effort from consumption results in the same irrationality as any other violation of the cost principle that
governs free markets. Because the disutility and the benefit of labor are not both fully internalized by the laborer, he is
unable to govern productive output in relation to consumption. The laborer produces a surplus because the market relation
between effort and consumption is distorted, and he does not receive the market signal to stop work when he had met his own
needs. Because labor pays tribute for access to the means of production, the total output necessary to receive a given level
of consumption is always greater than the amount consumed; meanwhile the rentier classes collect a surplus income for which
they did not labor. The producing classes therefore create a surplus, not for their own consumption, but to be piled up by
a privileged class that cannot possibly dispose of it all.
In the end, Hobson failed to isolate the "taproot" of this phenomenon. His analysis repeatedly grazed the true nature of
the problem, without ever directly hitting it. The problem is not the failure to distribute income according to "need," but
according to work: labor does not receive its full product as a wage. And the solution is not the Keynesian redistribution
of income by the state from rich to poor, but an end to the state's existing redistribution of income from poor to rich. Thomas
Hodgskin had stuck nearer the real root of the problem a couple of generations earlier:
The wants of individuals which labour is intended to gratify, are the natural guides to their exertions. The instant they
are compelled to labour for others, this guide forsakes them, and their exertions are dictated by the greed and avarice, and
false hopes of their masters. The wants springing from our organization, and accompanying the power to labour, being created
by the same hand which creates and fashions the whole universe, ...it is fair to suppose that they would at all times guide
the exertions of the labourer, so as fully to ensure a supply of necessaries and conveniences, and nothing more.... By this
system [of the avarice and greed of masters] the hand is dissevered from the mouth, and labour is put in motion to
gratify vanity and ambition, not the natural wants of animal existence. When we look at the commercial history of our country,
and see the false hopes of our merchants and manufacturers leading to periodical commercial convulsions, we are compelled
to conclude, that they have not the same source as the regular and harmonious external world. Capitalists have no guide to
their exertions, because nature rejects and opposes their dominion over labour. Starts of national prosperity, followed by
bankruptcy and ruin, have the same source then as fraud and forgery. To our legal [as opposed to natural] right of
property we are indebted for those gleams of false wealth and real panic, which have so frequently shook, to its centre, the
whole trading world.8
The concentration of the economy in corporate form, in subsequent years, only intensified these inherent tendencies toward
crisis.
Nevertheless, despite their faulty understanding of the reasons for the crisis, both business and government resounded
with claims that U.S. productive capacity had outstripped the domestic market's ability to consume, and that the government
had to take active measures to obtain outlets. We proceed to a brief survey of typical remarks from business and government
leaders in the years following the depression of the 1890s. In reading the quotes over the next few pages, it's worth bearing
in mind that they are not the ravings of Marxist ideologues; they are, rather, the measured reflections of sound, conservative
businessmen. The theory of imperialism was the creation, not of Lenin, but of corporate leaders.
In 1897 NAM president Theodore C. Search said, "Many of our manufacturers have outgrown or are outgrowing their home
markets, and the expansion of our foreign trade is our only promise of relief."9 In the same year, Albert J.
Beveridge proclaimed: "American factories are making more than the American people can use; American soil is producing
more than they can consume. Fate has written our policy for us; the trade of the world must and shall be ours."10
As the State Department's Bureau of Foreign Commerce put it in 1898,
It seems to be conceded that every year we shall be confronted with an increasing surplus of manufactured goods for sale
in foreign markets if American operatives and artisans are to be kept employed the year around. The enlargement of foreign
consumption of the products of our mills and workshops has, therefore, become a serious problem of statesmanship as well as
of commerce.11
In 1900, former Secretary of State John W. Foster wrote, "it has come to be a necessity to find new and enlarged markets
for our agricultural and manufactured products. We cannot maintain our present industrial prosperity without them."12
Ohio governor McKinley emerged as spokesman for this new American consensus, proposing a combination of protective tariffs
and reciprocity treaties to open foreign markets to American surplus output with help from the state.13 As keynote
speaker at an organizational meeting of the National Association of Manufacturers in 1895, he said:
We want our own markets for our manufactures and agricultural products.... [W]e want a foreign market for our surplus
products.... We want a reciprocity which will give us foreign markets for our surplus products, and in turn that will open
our markets to foreigners for those products which they produce and we do not.14
The imperialism of McKinley and Roosevelt, and the resulting Spanish-American War, were outgrowths of this orientation.
They were not, however, the only or obvious form of state policy for securing foreign markets. Much more typical of U.S. policy,
in the coming years, was the orientation outlined in John Hay's Open Door Notes (the first was written in 1899), which
Williams called "Open Door Empire."
A. "Open Door Imperialism" Through the 1930s.
Open Door imperialism consisted of using U.S. political power to guarantee access to foreign markets and resources on terms
favorable to American corporate interests, without relying on direct political rule. Its central goal was to obtain for U.S.
merchandise, in each national market, treatment equal to that afforded any other industrial nation. Most importantly, this
entailed active engagement by the U.S. government in breaking down the imperial powers' existing spheres of economic influence
or preference. The result, in most cases, was to treat as hostile to U.S. security interests any large-scale attempt at autarky,
or any other policy whose effect was to withdraw a major area from the disposal of U.S. corporations. When the power attempting
such policies was an equal, like the British Empire, the U.S. reaction was merely one of measured coolness. When it was perceived
as an inferior, like Japan, the U.S. resorted to more forceful measures, as events of the late 1930s indicate. And whatever
the degree of equality between advanced nations in their access to Third World markets, it was clear that Third World nations
were still to be subordinated to the industrialized West in a collective sense. Indeed, one think that Kautsky had the Open
Door in mind in formulating his theory of "ultra-imperialism," in which the developed capitalist nations cooperated to exploit
the Third World collectively.15
This Open Door system was the direct ancestor of today's neoliberal system, which is falsely called "free trade" in the
apologetics of court intellectuals. It depended on active management of the world economy by dominant states, and continuing
intervention to police the international economic order and enforce sanctions against states which did not cooperate. Woodrow
Wilson, in a 1907 lecture at Columbia University, said:
Since trade ignores national boundaries and the manufacturer insists on having the world as a market, the flag of his nation
must follow him, and the doors of the nations which are closed must be battered down.... Concessions obtained by financiers
must be safeguarded by ministers of state, even if the sovereignty of unwilling nations be outraged in the process. Colonies
must be obtained or planted, in order that no useful corner of the world may be overlooked or left unused. Peace itself becomes
a matter of conference and international combinations.16
Wilson warned during the 1912 election that "Our industries have expanded to such a point that they will burst their
jackets if they cannot find a free [i.e., guaranteed by the state] outlet to the markets of the world."17
In a 1914 address to the National Foreign Trade Convention, Secretary of Commerce Redfield followed very nearly the same
theme:
...we have learned the lesson now, that our factories are so large that their output at full time is greater than
America's market can continuously absorb. We know now that if we will run full time all the time, we must do it by
reason of the orders we take from lands beyond the sea. To do less than that means homes in America in which the husbands
are without work; to do that means factories that are shut down part of the time.18
Under the Open Door system, the state and its loans were to play a central role in the export of capital. The primary purpose
of foreign loans, historically, has been to finance the infrastructure which is a prerequisite for the establishment of enterprises
in foreign countries. As Edward E. Pratt, chief of the Bureau of Foreign and Domestic Commerce, said in 1914:
...we can never hope to realize the really big prizes in foreign trade until we are prepared to loan capital to foreign
nations and to foreign enterprise. The big prizes... are the public and private developments of large proportions, ...the
building of railroads, the construction of public-service plants, the improvement of harbors and docks, ...and many others
which demand capital in large amounts.... It is commonly said that trade follows the flag. It is much more truly said that
trade follows the investment or the loan.19
It was, however, beyond the resources of individual firms or venture capitalists, or of the decentralized banking system,
to raise the sums necessary for these tasks. One purpose of creating a central banking system (the Federal Reserve Act, 1914)
was to make possible the large-scale mobilization of investment capital for overseas ventures. Under the New Deal, the mobilization
began to take the form of direct state loans.20 The state's financial policies, besides promoting the accumulation
of capital for foreign investment, also underwrite foreign consumption of U.S. produce. As John Foster Dulles said in 1928,
"We must finance our exports by loaning foreigners the where-with-all to pay for them...."21 These two functions
were perfected in the Bretton Woods system after WWII.
B. The Bretton Woods System: Culmination of Open Door Empire
The second Roosevelt's administration saw the guarantee of American access to foreign markets as vital to ending the Depression
and the threat of internal upheaval that went along with it. Assistant Secretary of State Francis Sayre, chairman of Roosevelt's
Executive Committee on Commercial Policy, warned: "Unless we can export and sell abroad our surplus production, we must
face a violent dislocation of our whole domestic economy."22 FDR's ongoing policy of Open Door Empire, faced
with the withdrawal of major areas from the world market by the autarkic policies of the Greater East Asia Co-Prosperity Sphere
and Fortress Europe, led to American entry into World War II, and culminated in the postwar establishment of what Samuel Huntington
called a "system of world order" guaranteed both by global institutions of economic governance like the IMF, and by a hegemonic
political and military superpower.
In 1935, a War Department memorandum described the emerging Japanese threat in primarily economic terms. Japanese hegemony
over Asia, it warned, would have "a direct influence on those people of Europe and America who depend on trade and commerce
with this area for their livelihood." Germany, likewise, was defined as an "aggressor" because of its trade policies in
Latin America.23
After the fall of western Europe in the spring of 1940, Assistant Secretary of State Breckinridge Long warned that "every
commercial order will be routed to Berlin and filled under its orders somewhere in Europe rather than in the United States,"
resulting in "falling prices and declining profits here and a lowering of our standard of living with the consequent social
and political disturbances."24
Beginning in the Summer of 1940, the CFR and State Department undertook a joint study to determine the minimum portion
of the world the U.S. would have to integrate with its own economy, in order to provide sufficient resources and markets for
economic stability; it also explored policy options for reconstructing the postwar world.25 The study group found
that Germany's continental system was far more self-sufficient in resources, and more capable of autarky, than was the United
States. The U.S. economy could not survive in its existing form without access to the resources and markets not only of the
Western Hemisphere, but of the British Empire and Far East (together called the Grand Area). But the latter region was rapidly
being incorporated into Japan's economic sphere of influence. FDR made the political decision to contest Japanese power in
the Far East, and if necessary to initiate war. In the end, however, he successfully maneuvered Japan into firing the first
shot.26 The American policy that emerged from these struggles was one of securing control over the markets and
resources of the global "Grand Area" through institutions of global economic governance, reflected in the postwar Bretton
Woods system.
The problem of access to foreign markets and resources was central to U.S. policy planning for a postwar world. Given the
structural imperatives of "export dependent monopoly capitalism," the fear of a postwar depression was a real one. The original
drive toward foreign expansion at the end of the nineteenth century reflected the fact that industry, with state capitalist
encouragement, had expanded far beyond the ability of the domestic market to consume its output. Even before World War II,
the state capitalist economy had serious trouble operating at the level of output needed for full utilization of capacity
and cost control. Military-industrial policy during the war greatly exacerbated the problem of over-accumulation, increasing
the value of plant and equipment by two-thirds at taxpayer expense. The end of the war, if followed by the traditional pattern
of demobilization, would result in a drastic reduction in orders to this overbuilt industry at the same time that over ten
million workers were dumped back into the civilian labor force. And four years of forced restraints on consumption had created
a vast backlog of savings with no outlet in the already overbuilt domestic economy.
In November 1944, Dean Acheson addressed the Congressional committee on Postwar Economic Policy and Planning. He stressed
the consequences if the war were be followed by a slide back into depression: "it seems clear that we are in for a very
bad time, so far as the economic and social position of the country is concerned. We cannot go through another ten years like
the ten years at the end of the twenties and the beginning of the thirties, without having the most far-reaching consequences
upon our economic and social system." The problem, he said, was markets, not production. "You don't have a problem
of production.... The important thing is markets. We have got to see that what the country produces is used and is sold under
financial arrangements which make its production possible." Short of the introduction of a command economy, with controls
over income and distribution to ensure the domestic consumption of all that was produced, Acheson said, the only way to achieve
full output and full employment was through access to foreign markets.27
A central facet of postwar economic policy, as reflected in the Bretton Woods agencies, was state intervention to guarantee
markets for the full output of U.S. industry and profitable outlets for surplus capital. The World Bank was designed to subsidize
the export of capital to the Third World, by financing the infrastructure without which Western-owned production facilities
could not be established there. According to Gabriel Kolko's 1988 estimate, almost two thirds of the World Bank's loans since
its inception had gone to transportation and power infrastructure.28 A laudatory Treasury Department report referred
to such infrastructure projects (comprising some 48% of lending in FY 1980) as "externalities" to business, and spoke glowingly
of the benefits of such projects in promoting the expansion of business into large market areas and the consolidation and
commercialization of agriculture.29
Besides the benefit of building "an internal infrastructure which is a vital prerequisite for the development of resources
and direct United States private investments," such banks (because they must be repaid in U.S. dollars) require the borrowing
nations "to export goods capable of earning them, which is to say, raw materials...."30
The International Monetary Fund was created to facilitate the purchase of American goods abroad, by preventing temporary
lapses in purchasing power as a result of foreign exchange shortages. It was "a very large international currency exchange
and credit-granting institution that could be drawn upon relatively easily by any country that was temporarily short of any
given foreign currency due to trade imbalances."31
The Bretton Woods system by itself, however, was not nearly sufficient to ensure the levels of output needed to keep production
facilities running at full capacity, or to absorb excess investment funds. First the Marshall Plan, and then the permanent
war economy of the Cold War, came to the rescue.
The Marshall Plan was devised in reaction to the impending economic slump predicted by the Council of Economic advisers
in early 1947 and the failure of Western Europe "to recover from the war and take its place in the American scheme of things."
Undersecretary of State for Economic Affairs Clayton declared that the central problem confronting the United States was the
disposal of its "great surplus."32 Dean Acheson defended the Marshall Plan in a May 1947 address:
The extreme need of foreign countries for American products is likely... to continue undiminished in 1948, while the capacity
of foreign countries to pay in commodities will be only slightly increased.... What do these facts of international life mean
for the United States and for United States foreign policy? ...the United States is going to have to undertake further emergency
financing of foreign purchases if foreign countries are to continue to buy in 1948 and 1949 the commodities which they need
to sustain life and at the same time rebuild their economies....33
One New Deal partisan implicitly compared foreign economic expansion to domestic state capitalism as analogous forms of
surplus disposal: "it is as if we were building a TVA every Tuesday."34
The permanent war economy, however, had another advantage over projects like the TVA that produced use-value for the civilian
population: since it did not produce consumer goods, it did not add to the undisposable surplus or compete with the output
of private capital in consumer markets. In the apt words of Immanuel Goldstein: "Even when weapons of war are not actually
destroyed, their manufacture is still a convenient way of expending labor power without producing anything that can be consumed."
War is a way of "shattering to pieces, or pouring into the stratosphere, or sinking in the depths of the sea," excess
output and capital.35
Besides facilitating the export of goods and capital, the Bretton Woods agencies play a central role in the discipline
of recalcitrant regimes. There is a considerable body of radical literature on the Left on the use of debt as a political
weapon to impose pro-corporate policies (e.g., the infamous "structural adjustment program") on Third World governments, analogous
to the historic function of debt in keeping miners and sharecroppers in their place.36 Cheryl Payer compared Third
World debt to individual debt peonage, in that the aim of the latter was "neither to collect the debt once and for all,
nor to starve the employee to death, but rather to keep the labourer permanently indentured through his debt to his employer...."37
David Korten argued, likewise:
The very process of the borrowing that created the indebtedness that gave the World Bank and the IMF the power to dictate
the policies of borrowing countries represented an egregious assault on the principles of democratic accountability. Loan
agreements, whether with the World Bank, the IMF, other official lending institutions, or commercial banks, are routinely
negotiated in secret between banking officials and a handful of government officials--who in many instances are themselves
unelected and unaccountable to the people on whose behalf they are obligating the national treasury to foreign lenders. Even
in democracies, the borrowing procedures generally bypass the normal appropriation processes of democratically elected legislative
bodies. Thus, government agencies are able to increase their own budgets without legislative approval, even though the legislative
body will have to come up with the revenues to cover repayment. Foreign loans also enable governments to increase current
expenditures without the need to raise current taxes--a feature that is especially popular with wealthy decision makers. The
same officials who approve the loans often benefit directly through participation in contracts and "commissions" from grateful
contractors. The system creates a powerful incentive to over-borrow.38
Another way the Bretton Woods agencies exercise political power over recalcitrant regimes is the punitive withholding of
aid. This powerful political weapon has been used at times to undermine elective democracies whose policies fell afoul of
corporate interests, and to reward compliant dictatorships. For example, the World Bank refused to lend to the Goulart government
in Brazil; but following the installation of a military dictatorship by the 1964 coup, the Bank's lending averaged $73 million
a year for the rest of the decade, and reached almost a half-billion by the mid-70s. Chile, before and after the Pinochet
coup, followed a similar pattern.39 Or as Ambassador Korry warned, in the latter-day equivalent of a papal interdict,
"Not a nut or bolt shall reach Chile under Allende. Once Allende comes to power we shall do all within our power to condemn
Chile and all Chileans to utmost deprivation and poverty."40
Cheryl Payer's The Debt Trap is an excellent historical survey of the use of debt crises to force countries into
standby arrangements, precipitate coups, or provoke military crackdowns. In addition to their use against Goulart and Allende,
as mentioned above, she provides case studies of the Suharto coup in Indonesia and Marcos' declaration of martial law in the
Phillippines. Walden Bello, in Development Debacle,41 goes into much greater depth on the Phillippines specifically,
based on extensive documentation of World Bank collaboration with Marcos in support of the authoritarian crackdown preceding
his austerity programs.
Among the many features of the so-called structural adjustment program, mentioned above, the policy of "privatization"
(by selling state assets to "latter-day Reconstructionists," as Sean Corrigan says below) stands out. Joseph Stromberg described
the process, as it has been used by the Iraq Provisional Authority, as "funny auctions, that amounted to new expropriations
by domestic and foreign investors...." Such auctions of state properties will "likely lead... to a massive alienation
of resources into the hands of select foreign interests."42
The promotion of unaccountable, technocratic Third World governments, insulated from popular pressure and closely tied
to international financial elites, has been a central goal of Bretton Woods agencies since World War II.
From the 1950s onwards, a primary focus of [World] Bank policy was "institution-building", most often taking the
form of promoting the creation of autonomous agencies within governments that would be continual World Bank borrowers. Such
agencies were intentionally established to be independent financially from their host governments, as well as minimally accountable
politically--except, of course, to the Bank.43
The World Bank created the Economic Development Institute in 1956 specifically to enculture Third World elites into the
values of the Bretton Woods system. It offered a six-month course in "the theory and practice of development," whose 1300
alumni by 1971 included prime ministers, ministers of planning, and ministers of finance.44
The creation of such patronage networks has been one of the World Bank's most important strategies for inserting itself
in the political economies of Third World countries. Operating according to their own charters and rules (frequently drafted
in response to Bank suggestions), and staffed with rising technocrats sympathetic, even beholden, to the Bank, the agencies
it has funded have served to create a steady, reliable source of what the Bank needs most--bankable loan proposals. They have
also provided the Bank with critical power bases through which it has been able to transform national economies, indeed whole
societies, without the bothersome procedures of democratic review and discussion of the alternatives.45
Despite the vast body of scholarly literature on the issues discussed in this passage, perhaps the most apt description
of it was a pithy comment by a free market libertarian, Sean Corrigan:
Does he [Treasury Secretary O'Neill] not know that the whole IMF-US Treasury carpet-bagging strategy of full-spectrum
dominance is based on promoting unproductive government-led indebtedness abroad, at increasingly usurious rates of interest,
and then--either before or, more often these days, after, the point of default--bailing out the Western banks who have been
the agents provocateurs of this financial Operation Overlord, with newly-minted dollars, to the detriment of the citizenry
at home?
Is he not aware that, subsequent to the collapse, these latter-day Reconstructionists must be allowed to swoop and to buy
controlling ownership stakes in resources and productive capital made ludicrously cheap by devaluation, or outright monetary
collapse?
Does he not understand that he must simultaneously coerce the target nation into sweating its people to churn out export
goods in order to service the newly refinanced debt, in addition to piling up excess dollar reserves as a supposed bulwark
against future speculative attacks (usually financed by the same Western banks’ lending to their Special Forces colleagues
at the macro hedge funds) - thus ensuring the reverse mercantilism of Rubinomics is maintained?46
The American economy could have had access to the resources it was willing to buy on mutually satisfactory terms, and marketed
its own surplus to those countries willing to buy it, without the apparatus of transnational corporate mercantilism. Such
a state of affairs would have been genuine free trade. What the American elite really wanted, however, has been ably stated
by Thomas Friedman in one of his lapses into frankness:
For globalism to work, America can't be afraid to act like the almighty superpower it is.... The hidden hand of the market
will never work without a hidden fist--McDonald's cannot flourish without McDonnell Douglas, the designer of the F-15. And
the hidden fist that keeps the world safe for Silicon Valley's technologies is called the United States Army, Air Force, Navy
and Marine Corps.47
It was not true that the American corporate economy was ever in any real danger of losing access to the raw materials it
needed, in the absence of an activist foreign policy to secure access to those resources. As free market advocates often point
out, countries with disproportionate mineral wealth--say, large oil reserves--are forced to center a large part of their economic
activity on the extraction and sale of those resources. And once they sell them, the commodities enter a world market in which
it is virtually impossible to control who eventually buys them. The real issue, according to Baran and Sweezy, is that the
American corporate economy depended on access to Third World resources on favorable terms set by the United States, and those
favorable terms depended on the survival of pliable regimes.
But this [genuine free trade in resources with the Third World on mutually acceptable terms] is not what really
interests the giant multinational corporations which dominate American policy. What they want is monopolistic control
over foreign sources of supply and foreign markets, enabling them to buy and sell on specially privileged terms, to shift
orders from one subsidiary to another, to favor this country or that depending on which has the most advantageous tax, labor,
and other policies--in a word, they want to do business on their own terms and wherever they choose. And for this what they
need is not trading partners but "allies" and clients willing to adjust their laws and policies to the requirements of American
Big Business.48
The "system of world order" enforced by the U.S. since World War II, and lauded in Friedman's remarks about the "visible
hand," is nearly the reverse of the classical liberal notion of free trade. This new version of "free trade" is aptly characterized
in a passage by Christopher Layne and Benjamin Schwarz:
The view that economic interdependence compels American global strategic engagement puts an ironic twist on liberal internationalist
arguments about the virtues of free trade, which held that removing the state from international transactions would be an
antidote to war and imperialism....
....Instead of subscribing to the classical liberal view that free trade leads to peace, the foreign policy community looks
to American military power to impose harmony so that free trade can take place. Thus, U.S. security commitments are viewed
as the indispensable precondition for economic interdependence.49
Oliver MacDonagh pointed out that the modern neoliberal conception, far from agreeing with Cobden's idea of free trade,
resembled the "Palmerstonian system" that the Cobdenites so despised. Cobden objected, among other things, to the "dispatch
of a fleet 'to protect British interests' in Portugal," to the "loan-mongering and debt-collecting operations in which
our Government engaged either as principal or agent," and generally, all "intervention on behalf of British creditors
overseas." Cobden favored the "natural" growth of free trade, as opposed to the forcible opening of markets. Genuine free
traders opposed the confusion of "free trade" with "mere increases of commerce or with the forcible 'opening up'
of markets."50
I can't resist quoting Joseph Stromberg's only half tongue-in-cheek prescription "How to Have Free Trade":
For many in the US political and foreign policy Establishment, the formula for having free trade would go something like
this: 1) Find yourself a global superpower; 2) have this superpower knock together the heads of all opponents and skeptics
until everyone is playing by the same rules; 3) refer to this new imperial order as "free trade;" 4) talk quite a bit about
"democracy." This is the end of the story except for such possible corollaries as 1) never allow rival claimants to arise
which might aspire to co-manage the system of "free trade"; 2) the global superpower rightfully in charge of world order must
also control the world monetary system....
The formula outlined above was decidedly not the 18th and 19th-century liberal view of free trade. Free traders like Richard
Cobden, John Bright, Frederic Bastiat, and Condy Raguet believed that free trade is the absence of barriers to goods crossing
borders, most particularly the absence of special taxes--tariffs--which made imported goods artificially dear, often for the
benefit of special interests wrapped in the flag under slogans of economic nationalism....
Classical free traders never thought it necessary to draw up thousands of pages of detailed regulations to implement free
trade. They saw no need to fine-tune a sort of Gleichschaltung (co-ordination) of different nations labor laws, environmental
regulations, and the host of other such issues dealt with by NAFTA, GATT, and so on. Clearly, there is a difference between
free trade, considered as the repeal, by treaty or even unilaterally, of existing barriers to trade, and modern "free trade"
which seems to require truckloads of regulations pondered over by legions of bureaucrats.
This sea-change in the accepted meaning of free trade neatly parallels other characteristically 20th-century re-definitions
of concepts like "war," "peace," "freedom," and "democracy," to name just a few. In the case of free trade I think we can
deduce that when, from 1932 on, the Democratic Party-- with its traditional rhetoric about free trade in the older sense--took
over the Republicans project of neo-mercantilism and economic empire, it was natural for them to carry it forward under the
"free trade" slogan. They were not wedded to tariffs, which, in their view, got in the way of implementing Open Door Empire.
Like an 18th-century Spanish Bourbon government, they stood for freer trade within an existing or projected mercantilist system.
They would have agreed, as well, with Lord Palmerston, who said in 1841, "It is the business of Government to open and secure
the roads of the merchant." ....
Here, John A. Hobson... was directly in the line of real free-trade thought. Hobson wrote that businessmen ought to take
their own risks in investing overseas. They had no right to call on their home governments to "open and secure" their markets.51
And by the way, it's doubtful that superpower competition with the Soviets had much to do with the role of the U.S. in
shaping the postwar "system of world order," or in acting as "hegemonic power" in maintaining that system of order. Layne
and Schwarz cited NSC-68 to the effect that the policy of "attempting to develop a healthy international community"
was "a policy which we would probably pursue even if there were no Soviet threat."
Underpinning U.S. world order strategy is the belief that America must maintain what is in essence a military protectorate
in economically critical regions to ensure that America's vital trade and financial relations will not be disrupted by political
upheaval. This kind of economically determined strategy articulated by the foreign policy elite ironically (perhaps unwittingly)
embraces a quasi-Marxist or, more correctly, a Leninist interpretation of American foreign relations.52
The policy planners who designed the Bretton Woods system and the rest of the postwar framework of world order, apparently,
paid little or no mind to the issue of Soviet Russia's prospective role in the world. The record that appears, rather, in
Shoup and Minter's heavily documented account, is full of references to the U.S. as a successor to Great Britain as guarantor
of a global political and economic order, and to U.S. global hegemony as a war aim (even before the U.S. entered the war).
As early as 1942, when Soviet Russia's continued existence was very much in doubt, U.S. policy makers were referring to "domination
after the war," "Pax Americana," and "world control." To quote G. William Domhoff, "the definition of the national interest
that led to these interventions was conceived in the years 1940-42 by corporate planners in terms of what they saw as the
needs of the American capitalist system, well before communism was their primary concern."53
Considering the continuity in the pattern of U.S. Third World intervention during the Cold War with its gunboat diplomacy
of the 20s and 30s, or with its actions as the world's sole superpower since the fall of communism, should also be instructive.
Indeed, since the collapse of the USSR, the U.S. has been frantically scrambling to find (or create) another enemy sufficient
to justify continuing its role as world policeman.
Despite Chomsky's periodic rhetorical excesses, his characterization of the postwar era was essentially correct: "Putting
second-order complexities to the side, for the USSR the Cold War has been primarily a war against its satellites, and for
the US a war against the Third World. For each, it has served to entrench a particular system of domestic privilege and coercion."54
If anything, the Cold War with the Soviet Union appears almost as an afterthought to American planning for a postwar order.
Far from being the cause of the U.S. role as guarantor of a system of world order, the Soviet Empire acted as a spoiler to
preexisting U.S. plans for acting as a sole global superpower. Historically, any rival power which has refused to be incorporated
into the Grand Area, or which has encouraged other countries (by "defection from within") to withdraw from the Grand Area,
has been viewed as an "aggressor." Quoting Domhoff once again,
....I believe that anticommunism became a key aspect of foreign policy only after the Soviet Union, China, and their Communist
party allies became the challengers to the Grand Area conception of the national interest. In a certain sense..., they merely
replaced the fascists of Germany and Japan as the enemies of the international economic and political system regarded as essential
by American leaders.55
Likewise, as Domhoff's last sentence in the above quote suggests, any country which has interfered with U.S. attempts to
integrate the markets and resources of any region of the world into its international economic order has been viewed as a
"threat." The Economic and Financial Group of the CFR/State Department postwar planning project, produced, on July 24, 1941,
a document (E-B34), warning of the need for the United States to "defend the Grand Area," not only against external
attack by Germany, but against "defection from within," particularly against countries like Japan (which, along with
the rest of east Asia, was regarded as part of the Grand Area) bent on "destroying the area for its own political reasons."56
The centrality of this consideration is illustrated by the report of a 1955 study group of the Woodrow Wilson Center, which
pointed to the threat of "a serious reduction in the potential resource base and market opportunities of the West owing
to the subtraction of the communist areas and their economic transformation in ways that reduce their willingness and ability
to complement the industrial economies of the West."57
One way of defending against "defection from within" is to ensure that Third World countries have the right kind of government.
That can be done either by supporting authoritarian regimes, or what neoconservatives call "democracy." The key quality for
Third World elites, in either case, is an orientation toward what Thomas Barnett calls "connectivity." The chief danger presented
by "outlaw regimes," according to Barnett, lies in their being disconnected "from the globalizing world, from its rule
sets, its norms, and all the ties that bind countries together in mutually assured dependence."58
The neoconservative version of democracy is more or less what Noam Chomsky means by "spectator democracy": a system in
which the public engages in periodic legitimation rituals called "elections," choosing from a narrow range of candidates all
representing the same elite. Having thus done its democratic duty, the public returns to bowling leagues and church socials,
and other examples of "civil society," and leaves the mechanics of policy to its technocratic betters--who immediately proceed
to take orders from the World Bank and IMF. This form of democracy is nearly synonymous with what neocons call "the rule of
law," which entails a healthy dose of Weberian bureaucratic rationality. The stability and predictability associated with
such "democracies" is, from the business standpoint, greatly preferable to the messiness of dictatorship or death squads.
American "pro-democratic" policy in the Third World, traditionally, has identified "democracy" with electoralism, and little
else. In Central America, for example, a country is viewed as a "democracy" if its government "came to power through free
and fair elections." But this policy ignores the vital dimension of popular participation, "including the free expression
of opinions, day-to-day interaction between the government and the citizenry, the mobilization of interest groups," etc.
The "underlying objective" of pro-democracy policies is "to maintain the basic order of what... are quite undemocratic
societies." Democracy is a means of "relieving pressure for more radical change," but only through "limited,
top-down forms of democratic change that [do] not risk upsetting the traditional structures of power with which the
United States has been allied."59 Democracy policy in El Salvador, more specifically, promoted a form of "democracy"
through the Duarte regime that did not touch the power of the military or the landed elite.60
American elites prefer "democracy" whenever possible, but will resort to dictatorship in a pinch. The many, many cases
in which the U.S. Assistance Program, the School of the Americas, the CIA, the World Bank and IMF, and others from the list
of usual suspects have collaborated in just this expedient are recounted, in brutal detail, by William Blum in Killing
Hope.61
Even an authoritarian communist regime is preferable, as an ultimate last resort, to a democracy that pursues a genuinely
populist agenda, like the Arbenz regime in Guatemala. To prevent the latter development, the U.S. will risk a country falling
to genuine Marxist-Leninists. It is obvious that the primary concern behind the typical Third World intervention was not the
danger of an alliance between that country and Soviet strategic power. Had anti-communism been the U.S. government's main
preoccupation, and not economic control, its policy would have been much different.
While there were many varieties of capitalism consistent with the anti-Communist politics the United States... sought to
advance, what was axiomatic in the American credo was that the form of capitalism it advocated for the world was to be integrated
in such a way that its businessmen played an essential part in it. Time and again it was ready to sacrifice the most
effective way of opposing Communism in order to advance its own national interests. In this vital sense its world role was
not simply one of resisting the left but primarily of imposing its own domination....
....[I]t was its clash with nationalist elements, as diverse as they were, that revealed most about the U.S. global
crusade, for had fear of Communism alone been the motivation of its behavior, the number of obstacles to its goals would have
been immeasurably smaller.62
An authoritarian communist regime, like the pigs on Animal Farm, can be quite reasonable in dealing with its neighboring
farmers. The Chinese "workers' paradise," a favorite haven for foreign sweatshops, is a prime example.
The chief necessity, as we saw above, is that a Third World country's economic policy be made by a domestic elite that
is safely insulated from real accountability to the native population, and at the same time amenable to the policy goals and
values of transnational elites in such bodies as the World Bank and IMF. In the last couple of years we have seen this to
be true of the new regime in Afghanistan, headed by a man noted for his history of collaboration with the latter agencies;
of the Iraqi occupation government, or Iraq Provisional Authority, of which a high priority was the adoption of new laws to
enforce international copyrights.
C. Export-Dependent Monopoly Capitalism (with Digression on Economy of Scale)
According to Stromberg and the Austrians, the chronic problem of surplus output was not a natural result of the free market,
but rather of a cartelized economy. As we saw earlier, J.A. Hobson argued that "over-saving" was caused by "rents,
monopoly profits, and other unearned excessive profits," and called, in proto-Keynesian fashion, for the state to step
in and remedy the problem of "mal-distribution of consuming power."63 Those making such arguments are commonly
dismissed, on the libertarian right, as ignorant of Say's Law.
But Say's Law applies only to a free market. As Stromberg points out, a genuine maldistribution of consuming power results
from the state's intervention to transfer wealth from its real producers to a politically connected ruling class. And neo-Marxists'
work on over-accumulation has shown us that the evils that Keynesianism was designed to remedy, in a state capitalist economy,
are quite real. The State promotes the accumulation of capital on a scale beyond which its output can be absorbed (at its
cartelized prices) by private demand; and therefore capital relies on the State to dispose of this surplus.
One of the earliest to describe the the several aspects of the phenomenon was Hilferding, in Finance Capital:
The curtailment of production means the cessation of all new capital investment, and the maintenance of high prices makes
the effects of the crisis more severe for all those industries which are not cartelized, or not fully cartelized. Their profits
will fall more sharply, or their losses will be greater, than is the case in the cartelized industries, and in consequence
they will be obliged to make greater cuts in production. As a result, disproportionality will increase, he sales of cartelized
industry will suffer more, and it becomes evident that in spite of the severe curtailment of production, "overproduction"
persists and has even increased. Any further limitation of production means that more capital will be idle, while overheads
remain the same, so that the cost per unit will rise, thus reducing profits still more despite the maintenance of high prices.64
All the elements are here, in rough form: the expansion of production facilities to a scale beyond what the market will
support; the need to restrict output to keep up prices, conflicting with the simultaneous need to keep output high enough
to utilize full capacity and keep unit costs down; the inability of the economy to absorb the full output of cartelized industry
at monopoly prices.
But as Hilferding pointed out in the same passage, the natural tendency in such a situation, in the absence of entry barriers,
would be for competitors to enter the market and drive down the monopoly price: "The high prices attract outsiders, who
can count on low capital and labor costs, since all other prices have fallen; thus they establish a strong competitive position
and begin to undersell the cartel."65 This, Rothbard argued, is what normally happens when cartelizing ventures
are not backed up by the state: they are broken either by internal defection or by new entrants. That is, in fact, what Gabriel
Kolko described as actually happening to the trust movement at the turn of the century. Therefore, organized capital depends
on the state to enforce an artificial monopoly on the domestic market.
By restricting production quotas for domestic consumption the cartel eliminates competition on the domestic market. The
suppression of competition sustains the effect of a protective tariff in raising prices even at a stage when production has
long since outstripped demand. Thus it becomes a prime interest of cartelized industry to make the protective tariff a permanent
institution, which in the first place assures continued existence of the cartel, and second, enables the cartel to sell its
product on the domestic market at an extra profit.66
And, Hilferding continued, cartelized industry is forced to dispose of the surplus product, which will not sell domestically
at the monopoly price, by dumping it on foreign markets.
The increase in prices on the domestic market... tends to reduce the sales of cartelized products, and thus conflicts with
the trend towards lowering costs by expanding the scale of production.... But if a cartel is already well established, it
will try to compensate for the decline of the domestic market by increasing its exports, in order to continue production as
before and if possible on an even larger scale. If the cartel is efficient and capable of exporting... its real price of production...
will correspond with the world market price. But a cartel is also in a position to sell below its production price, because
it has obtained an extra profit, determined by the level of the protective tariff, from its sales on the domestic market.
It is therefore able to use a part of this extra profit to expand its sales abroad by underselling its competitors. If it
is successful it can then increase its output, reduce its costs, and thereby, since domestic prices remain unchanged, gain
further extra profit.67
Further, anticipating the various Marxist theories of imperialism, Hilferding argued that this imperative of disposing
of surplus product abroad requires the activist state to seek foreign markets on favorable terms for domestic capital. One
such state policy is the promotion or granting of loans abroad, either by direct state loans, or by banking policies that
centralize the banking system and thus facilitate the accumulation of large sums of capital for foreign loans. Such loans
could be used to increase a country's purchasing power and increase its imports; but more importantly, they could be used
for building transportation and power infrastructure that Western capital requires for building production facilities in an
underdeveloped country.68 Of course, such direct foreign capital investment in a country, unlike mere trade, required
more direct political influence over the country's internal affairs to protect the investments from expropriation and labor
unrest.69
The state could also intervene to create a wage-labor force in backward countries by expropriating land, thus recreating
the process of primitive accumulation in the West. In addition, heavy taxation could be used to force a peasantry into the
money economy, by making them work (or work more) in the capitalist job market to raise tax-money. This was a common pattern,
Hilferding wrote: in the Third World as in the West earlier, " when capital's need for expansion meets obstacles that could
only be overcome much too slowly and gradually by purely economic means, it has recourse to the power of the state and uses
it for forcible expropriation in order to create the required free wage proletariat."70
Generally speaking, Third World countries provide numerous advantages for capital seeking a higher rate of return:
The state ensures that human labour in the colonies is available on terms which make possible extra profits.... The natural
wealth of the colonies likewise becomes a source of extra profits by lowering the price of raw materials.... The expulsion
or annihilation of the native population, or in the most favourable case their transformation from shepherds or hunters into
indentured slaves, or their confinement to small, restricted areas as peasant farmers, creates at one stroke free land which
has only a nominal price.71
In Imperialism, Bukharin returned repeatedly to the theme of government policy in promoting monopoly, thorough such
devices as tariffs, state loans, etc. In a passage on the effects of foreign loans, Bukharin anticipated today's use of foreign
aid and World Bank/IMF credit as coercive weapons on behalf of American corporations:
The transaction is usually accompanied by a number of stipulations, in the first place that which imposes upon the borrowing
country the duty to place orders with the creditor country (purchase of arms, ammunition, dreadnaughts, railroad equipment,
etc), and the duty to grant concessions for the construction of railways, tramways, telegraph and telephone lines, harbours,
exploitation of mines, timberlands, etc.72
As Kwame Nkrumah jibed, so-called "foreign aid" under neocolonialism would have been called foreign investment in the days
of old-style colonialism.73
Schumpeter, the theorist upon whom Stromberg relies most heavily, described the system as "export-dependent monopoly
capitalism":
Union in a cartel or trust confers various benefits on the entrepreneur--a saving in costs, a stronger position as against
the workers--but none of these compares with this one advantage: a monopolistic price policy, possible to any considerable
degree only behind an adequate protective tariff. Now the price that bings the maximum monopoly profit is generally
far above the price that would be fixed by fluctuating competitive costs, and the volume that can be marketed at that maximum
price is generally far below the output that would be technically and economically feasible. Under free competition that output
would be produced and offered, but a trust cannot offer it, for it could be sold only at a competitive price. Yet the
trust must produce it--or approximately as much--otherwise the advantages of large-scale enterprise remain unexploited
and unit costs are likely to be uneconomically high.... [The trust] extricates itself from this dilemma by producing
the full output that is economically feasible, thus securing low costs, and offering in the protected domestic market only
the quantity corresponding to the monopoly price--insofar as the tariff permits; while the rest is sold, or "dumped," abroad
at a lower price....74
This process of "dumping" illustrated "Carnegie's law of surplus": "every manufacturer preferred to lose one dollar
by running full and holding markets by selling at lower prices than to lose two dollars by running less than full or close
down and run the risk of losing markets...."75
In describing the advantages of colonies for monopoly capitalism, Schumpeter essentially refuted his own Comtean argument
(discussed below in this article) for imperialism's "alien" status in relation to capitalism.
In such a struggle among "dumped" products and capitals, it is no longer a matter of indifference who builds a given railroad,
who owns a mine or a colony. Now that the law of costs is no longer operative, it becomes necessary to fight over such properties
with desperate effort and with every available means, including those that are not economic in character, such as diplomacy....
....In this context, the conquest of colonies takes on an altogether different significance. Non-monopolist countries,
especially those adhering to free trade, reap little profit from such a policy. But it is a different matter with countries
that function in a monopolistic role vis-a-vis their colonies. There being no competition, they can use
cheap native labor without its ceasing to be cheap; they can market their products, even in the colonies, at monopoly prices;
they can, finally, invest capital that would only depress the profit rate at home....76
Stromberg explained: "For American manufacturers to achieve available economies of scale, they had to produce far more
of their products than could be sold in the U.S."77
One point Stromberg does not adequately address here is that economy of scale, at least in terms of internal production
costs, requires only thorough utilization of existing facilities. But the size of the facilities was in itself the result
of state capitalist policies. The fact that domestic demand was not enough to support the output needed to reach such economies
of scale reflects the fact that the scale of production was too large. And this, in turn, was the result of state policies
that encouraged gigantism and overinvestment.
Productive economy of scale is "unlimited" only when the state absorbs the diseconomies of large scale production. Overall
economies of scale reflect a package of costs. And those costs are themselves influenced by direct and indirect subsidies
that distort price as an accurate signal of the actual cost of providing a service. If the state had not allowed big business
to externalize many of its operating costs (especially long-distance shipping) on the public through subsidies (especially
subsidized transportation), economy of scale would have been reached at a much lower level of production. The state's subsidies
have the effect of artificially shifting the economy of scale upward to higher levels of output than a free market can support.
State capitalism enables corporate interests to control elements of the total cost package through political means; but the
result is new imbalances, which in turn require further state intervention.
In fairness, Schumpeter touched on this issue in passing, as did Stromberg in quoting him: "a firm which could not survive
in the absence of empire was 'expanded beyond economically justifiable limits'."78 As this quote indicates,
Schumpeter dealt, though inadequately, with the extent to which corporate size was the effect of state intervention. He agreed
with Rothbard that cartelization or monopoly, as such, could not exist without the state.
Export monopolism does not grow from the inherent laws of capitalist development. The character of capitalism leads
to large-scale production, but with few exceptions large-scale production does not lead to the kind of unlimited concentration
that would leave but one or only a few firms in each industry. On the contrary, any plant runs up against limits to its growth
in a given location; and the growth of combinations which would make sense under a system of free trade encounters limits
of organizational efficiency. Beyond these limits there is no tendency toward combination in the competitive system.79
Still, Stromberg greatly overestimates the advantages of large-scale production in a free market. In all but a few forms
of production, peak economy of scale is reached at relatively low levels of output. In agriculture, for instance, a USDA study
found in 1973 that economy of scale was maximized on a fully-mechanized one-man farm.80
Walter Adams and James Brock, two specialists in economy of scale, cited a number of studies showing that "optimum plant
sizes tend to be quite small relative to the national market." According to one study, even taking into account the efficiencies
of firm size, market shares of the top three firms in nine of twelve industries exceeded maximum efficiency by a factor of
anywhere from two to ten. But productive economy of scale was a function primarily of plant size, not the size of multi-plant
firms. Any efficiencies of bargaining power provided by large firm size were offset by increased administrative and control
costs, and other diseconomies.81 In fact, Seymor Melman argued that the increased administrative costs of multi-unit
and multi-product firms are astronomical. They are prone to many of the same inefficiencies--falsified data from below, and
"elaborate, formal systems of control, with accompanying police systems--as state-run industry in the communist countries.82
Describing the inefficiencies of large firms, Kenneth Boulding echoed Melman, but in more colorful language:
There is a great deal of evidence that almost all organizational structures tend to produce false images in the decision-maker,
and that the larger and more authoritarian the organization, the better the chance that its top decision-makers will be operating
in purely imaginary worlds.83
In the most capital-intensive industry, automobiles, peak economy of scale was achieved at a level of production equivalent
to 3-6% of market share.84 And even this level of output is required only because annual model changes (which arguably
wouldn't pay for themselves without state capitalist subsidies) require an auto plant to wear out the dies for a run of production
in a single year. Otherwise, peak economy of scale would be reached in a plant with an output of only 60,000 per year.85
In any case, these figures relate only to productive economy of scale. Increased distribution costs begin to offset increased
economies of production, according to Borsodi's law, long before peak productive economy of scale is reached. According to
an F.M. Scherer study cited by Adams and Brock, a plant producing at one-third the maximum efficiency level of output would
experience only a 5% increase in unit costs.86 This is more than offset by reduced shipping costs for a smaller
market.
The point of this digression is that the size of existing firms reflects the role of the state in subsidizing increased
size by underwriting the inefficiencies of corporate gigantism--as Rothbard pointed out, the ways "our corporate state
uses the coercive taxing power either to accumulate corporate capital or to lower corporate costs."87 A genuine
free market economy would be vastly less centralized, with production primarily for local markets.
Besides the problem of surplus output, the state capitalist economy produces a second problem: that of surplus capital.
Not only does monopoly pricing limit domestic demand, and thus restrain the opportunities for expansion at home; but non-cartelized
industry is seriously disadvantaged as a source of returns on capital, and therefore opportunities for profitable investment
are limited outside the cartelized sectors.
According to Hilferding, "while the drive to increase production is very strong in the cartelized industries, high cartel
prices preclude any growh of the domestic market, so that expansion abroad offers the best chance of meeting the need to increase
output."88 Bukharin later described the capital surplus as a direct result of cartelization, in quite similar
language. In Chapter VII of Imperialism and World Economy, he wrote:
The volumes of capital that seek employment have reached unheard of dimensions. On the other hand, the cartels and trusts,
as the modern organisation of capital, tend to put certain limits to the employment of capital by fixing the volume of production.
As to the non-trustified sections of industry, it becomes ever more unprofitable to invest capital in them. For monopoly organisations
can overcome the tendency towards lowering the rate of profit by receiving monopoly superprofits at the expense of the non-trustified
industries. Out of the surplus value created every year, one portion, that which has been created in the nontrustified branches
of industry, is being transferred to the co-owners of capitalist monopolies, whereas the share of the outsiders continually
decreases. Thus the entire process drives capital beyond the frontiers of the country.89
Monopoly capital theorists have made worthwhile contributions to the issue of capital and output surpluses. For example,
the surplus product of cartelized industry drastically increases the importance of the "sales effort"--what Galbraith called
"specific demand management" to dispose of the product.90 This underscores the importance of the state in the problem
of surplus disposal: without state intervention to create the national infrastructure of mass media and its attendant mass
advertising markets, specific demand management would have been impossible.
One issue Stromberg neglects is the internal role of the state in directly disposing of the surplus. The role of the State's
purchases in absorbing surplus output, through both military and domestic spending, was a key part of Baran and Sweezy's "monopoly
capitalism" model. Its large "defense" and other expenditures provide a guaranteed internal market for surplus output analogous
to that provided by state-guaranteed foreign markets. By providing such an internal market, the state increases the percentage
of production capacity that can be used on a consistent basis.91
Paul Mattick elaborated on this theme in a 1956 article. The overbuilt corporate economy, he wrote, ran up against the
problem that "[p]rivate capital formation... finds its limitation in diminishing market-demand." The State had to absorb
part of the surplus output; but it had to do so without competing with corporations in the private market. Instead, "[g]overnment-induced
production is channeled into non-market fields--the production of non-competitive public-works, armaments, superfluities and
waste.92 As a necessary result of this state of affairs,
so long as the principle of competitive capital production prevails, steadily growing production will in increasing measure
be a "production for the sake of production," benefiting neither private capital nor the population at large.
This process is somewhat obscured, it is true, by the apparent profitability of capital and the lack of large-scale unemployment.
Like the state of prosperity, profitability, too, is now largely government manipulated. Government spending and taxation
are managed so as to strengthen big business at the expense of the economy as a whole....
In order to increase the scale of production and to accummulate [sic] capital, government creates "demand" by ordering
the production of non-marketable goods, financed by government borrowings. This means that the government avails itself of
productive resources belonging to private capital which would otherwise be idle.93
Such consumption of output, while not always directly profitable to private industry, serves a function analogous to foreign
"dumping" below cost, in enabling the corporate economy to achieve economies of large-scale production at levels of output
beyond the ability of private consumers to absorb.
It's interesting to consider how many segments of the economy have a guaranteed market for their output, or a "conscript
clientele" in place of willing consumers. The "military-industrial complex" is well known. But how about the state's education
and penal systems? How about the automobile-trucking-highway complex, or the civil aviation complex? Foreign surplus disposal
("export dependant monopoly capitalism") and domestic surplus disposal (government purchases) are different forms of the same
phenomenon.
Marx described major new forms of industry as countervailing influences against the falling rate of profit. Baran and Sweezy,
likewise, considered "epoch-making inventions" as partial counterbalances to the ever-increasing surplus. Their chief example
of such a phenomenon was the rise of the automobile industry in the 1920s, which (along with the highway program) was to define
the American economy for most of the mid-20th century.94 The high tech boom of the 1990s was a similarly revolutionary
event. It is revealing to consider the extent to which both the automobile and computer industries, far more than most industries,
were direct products of state capitalism. More recently, in the Bush administration, to consider only one industry (pharmaceuticals),
two major policy initiatives benefit it by providing state-funded outlets for its production: the so-called "prescription
drug benefit," and the provision of AIDS drugs to destitute African countries. In another industry, Bush's R&D funding
for hydrogen fuel engines is enabling the automobile companies to develop the successor technology to the gasoline engine
(with patents included) at public expense; this not only subsidizes their transition to viability in a post-fossil fuel world,
but gives them monopoly control over the successor technology. "Creative destruction" is our middle name.
NOTES
1. William Appleman Williams, The Tragedy of American Diplomacy (New York: Dell Publishing Company, 1959, 1962)
21-2.
2. Ibid. 26.
3. J. A. Hobson, Imperialism: A Study (London: Archibald Constable & Co., Ltd, 1905) 66.
4. Ibid. 73.
5. Ibid. 74-5.
6. Ibid. 75-6.
7. Ibid. 76-7.
8. Thomas Hodgskin, The Natural and Artificial Right of Property Contrasted (London: B. Steil, 1832) 155-6.
9. Williams, Tragedy of American Diplomacy 27.
10. Ibid. 17.
11. Ibid. 17.
12. William Appleman Williams, The Contours of American History (Cleveland and New York: The World Publishing Company,
1961) 368.
13. Joseph R. Stromberg, "The Role of State Monopoly Capitalism in the American Empire" Journal of Libertarian Studies
Volume 15, no. 3 (Summer 2001) 61-3 http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/15_3/15_3_3.pdf Captured October 28, 2003).
14. Williams, Contours of American History 363-4.
15. Martin Sklar, The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism, 1890-1916: The Market, the Law, and Politics
(Cambridge, New York and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 82; Karl Kautsky, "Imperialism and the War," International
Socialist Review (November 1914), trans. by William E. Bohn http://www.marxists.org/archive/kautsky/works/1910s/war.html
Captured September 23, 2002.
16. Williams, Tragedy of American Diplomacy 66.
17. Martin J. Sklar, "Woodrow Wilson and the Political Economy of Modern United States Liberalism," in Murray Rothbard
and Ronald Radosh, eds., A New History of Leviathan: Essays on the Rise of the American Corporate State (New York:
E. P. Dutton & Co., Inc., 1972) 27.
18. Ibid. 40.
19. Ibid. 62n.
20. Williams, Tragedy of American Diplomacy 179.
21. Ibid. 123.
22. Ibid. 170.
23. Robert Freeman Smith, "American Foreign Relations, 1920-1942," in Barton J. Bledstein, ed., Towards a New Past:
Dissenting Essays in American History (New York: Vintage Books, 1967, 1968) 247.
24. Ibid. 247.
25. The rest of this paragraph, unless otherwise noted, is based on Laurence H. Shoup and William Minter, "Shaping a New
World Order: The Council on Foreign Relations' Blueprint for World Hegemony, 1939-1945," in Holly Sklar, ed., Trilateralism:
The Trilateral Commission and Elite Planning for World Management (Boston: South End Press, 1980) 135-56.
26. Robert Stinnett, Day of Deceit: The Truth About FDR and Pearl Harbor (New York: Free Press, 1999).
27. Williams, Tragedy of American Diplomacy 235-6.
28. Gabriel Kolko, Confronting the Third World: United States Foreign Policy 1945-1980 (New York: Pantheon Books,
1988) 120.
29. United States Participation in the Multilateral Development Banks in the 1980s. Department of the Treasury (Washingon,
DC: 1982) 9.
30. Gabriel Kolko, The Roots of American Foreign Policy: An Analysis of Power and Purpose (Boston: Beacon Press,
1969) 72.
31. G. William Domhoff, The Power Elite and the State: How Policy is Made in America (New York: Aldine de Gruyter,
1990) 166.
32. Ibid. 271.
33. Leonard P. Liggio, "American Foreign Policy and National Security Management," in Rothbard and Radosh, eds., New
History of Leviathan 249.
34. Williams, Tragedy of American Diplomacy 272.
35. George Orwell, 1984. Signet Classics reprint (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1949, 1981) 157.
36. Cheryl Payer, The Debt Trap: The International Monetary Fund and the Third World (New York: Monthly Review Press,
1974); Walden Bello, "Structural Adjustment Programs: 'Success' for Whom?" in Jerry Mander and Edward Goldsmith, eds., The
Case Against the Global Economy (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1996); Bruce Franklin. "Debt Peonage: The Highest Form
of Imperialism?" Monthly Review 33:10 (March 1982) 15-31.
37. Payer, Debt Trap 48-9.
38. David Korten, When Corporations Rule the World (West Hartford, Conn.: Kumarian Press, 1995; San Francisco, Calif.:
Berrett-Koehler, Publishers, Inc., 1995) 166.
39. Bruce Rich, "The Cuckoo in the Nest: Fifty Years of Political Meddling by the World Bank," The Ecologist (January/February
1994) 10.
40. Holly Sklar, "Overview," in Holly Sklar, ed., Trilateralism: The Trilateral Commission and Elite Planning for World
Management (Boston: South End Press, 1980) 28-9.
41. Walden Bello, Development Debacle: The World Bank in the Philippines (San Francisco: Institute for Food &
Development Policy, 1982).
42. Joseph R. Stromberg, "Experimental Economics, Indeed" Ludwig von Mises Institute, January 6, 2004 http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1409
Captured July 25, 2004.
43. Rich, "Cuckoo in the Nest" 9.
44. Ibid. 9-10.
45. Ibid. 10.
46. Sean Corrigan, "You Can't Say That!" August 6, 2002 http://www.lewrockwell.com/corrigan/corrigan13.html Captured August
6, 2002.
47. Thomas Friedman, "What the World Needs Now," New York Times, March 28, 1999.
48. Paul Baran and Paul Sweezy, Monopoly Capitalism: An Essay in the American Economic and Social Order (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 1966) 201.
49. Christopher Layne and Benjamin Shwartz, "American Hegemony Without an Enemy," Foreign Policy (Fall 1993) 12-3.
50. Oliver MacDonough, "The Anti-Imperialism of Free Trade," The Economic History Review (Second Series) 14:3 (1962)
.
51. Joseph R. Stromberg, "Free Trade, Mercantilism and Empire," February 28, 2000 http://www.antiwar.com/stromberg/s022800.html
Captured May 1, 2002.
52. Layne and Shwartz, "American Hegemony Without an Enemy" 5, 12.
53. Domhoff, Power Elite and the State 113.
54. Noam Chomsky, Deterring Democracy (New York: Hill and Wang, 1991, 1992) 28.
55. Domhoff, Power Elite and the State 145.
56. Ibid. 160-1.
57. William Yandell Elliot, ed., The Political Economy of American Foreign Policy (Holt, Rinehart & Winston,
1955) 42.
58. Thomas Barnett, "The Pentagon's New Map," Esquire March 2003 http://www.thomaspmbarnett.com/published/pentagonsnewmap.htm
Captured July 26, 2004.
59. Thomas Carothers, "The Reagan Years: The 1980s," in Abraham F. Lowenthal, ed., Exporting Democracy (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins, 1991) 117-8.
60. Ibid. 96-7.
61. William Blum. Killing Hope: U.S. Military and CIA Interventions Since World War II (Monroe, Maine: Common Courage
Press, 1995).
62. Kolko, Confronting the Third World 117, 123.
63. Hobson, Imperialism 75-6.
64. Rudolf Hilferding, Finance Capital, ed. and trans. By Tom Bottomore (London and Boston: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1910, 1981) 297.
65. Ibid. 297.
66. Ibid. 308.
67. Ibid. 309.
68. Ibid. 317-8.
69. Ibid. 321.
70. Ibid. 319-20.
71. Ibid. 328.
72. Nikolai Bukharin, Imperialism and World Economy (International Publishers, 1929 (written 1915-1917) http://www.marxists.org/archive/bukharin/works/1917/imperial/
Captured October 28, 2003 Chapter VII.
73. Kwame Nkrumah, Neo-Colonialism: The Last Stage of Imperialism (New York: International Publishers, 1965) 51.
74. Joseph Schumpeter, "Imperialism," in Imperialism, Social Classes: Two Essays by Joseph Schumpeter. Translated
by Heinz Norden. Introduction by Hert Hoselitz (New York: Meridian Books, 1955) 79-80.
75. Sklar, Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism 58.
76. Schumpeter, "Imperialism" 82-3.
77. Stromberg, "Role of State Monopoly Capitalism" 65.
78. Ibid. 71.
79. Schumpeter, "Imperialism" 88.
80. W. R. Bailey, The One-Man Farm, qt. in L. S. Stavrianos, The Promise of the Coming Dark Age (San Francisco:
W. H. Freeman and Co., 1976) 38.
81. Walter Adams and James Brock, The Bigness Complex (New York: Pantheon Books, 1986) 33-4, 45-6.
82. Seymour Melman, Profits Without Production (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1983) 80.
83. Qt. in Barry Stein, Size, Efficiency, and Community Enterprise (Cambridge, Mass.: Center for Community Economic
Development, 1974) 5.
84. Adams and Brock, Bigness Complex 38-9.
85. Mark J. Green, et al., eds., The Closed Enterprise System. Ralph Nader’s Study Group Report on Antitrust
Enforcement (New York: Grossman Publishers, 1972) 243-4.
86. Adams and Brock, The Bigness Complex 45-6.
87. Murray Rothbard, "Confessions of a Right-Wing Liberal," in Henry J. Silverman, ed., American Radical Thought: The
Libertarian Tradition (Lexington, Mass.: D.C. Heath and Co., 1970) p. 305.
88. Hilferding, Finance Capital 325.
89. Bukharin, Imperialism and World Economy Chapter VII.
90. Baran and Sweezy, Monopoly Capitalism 112-41.
91. Ibid. 112, 142-77, 207-17.
92. Paul Mattick, "The Economics of War and Peace," Dissent (Fall 1956) 377.
93. Ibid. 378-9.
94. Baran and Sweezy, Monopoly Capitalism 220.
|